|
In
the fall of 1906, the well-bred British statistician Francis
Galton left his home to check out the West of England Fat
Stock and Poultry Exhibition, a regional fair. Galton was
a man obsessed with two things: breeding and statistics. What
better place for an eminent Victorian to be than a fair where
he could witness first-hand the effects of good and bad breeding?
As he walked through the fair, Galton stumbled across a weight-judging
competition.
The
fair's organizers had selected one fat ox and soon hundreds
of fairgoers were lining up to place bets on the weight of
the finely dressed carcass.
These
bettors came from all walks of life, some may hardly have
known as much as the butchers and farmers with their inside
information. Based on no more than smalltalk, these non-experts
competed offering their best guess. Galton did not think much
of the enterprise employing the argument that the bettors
like most voters were rationally ignorant. "The average
competitor," he later wrote, "was probably as well
fitted for making a just estimate of the dressed weight of
the ox, as an average voter is of judging the merits of most
political issues on which he votes."
Alas,
the poor folks would have no clue, surmised Galton because
they were merely average. In keeping with the consciousness
of his refined class (this was the turn of the century, after
all) Galton believed that average people were capable of very
little. So being the inquisitive man of science and having
an open mind, Galton decided to run an experiment. After the
contest was over and prizes distributed, Galton borrowed the
tickets from the fair's organizers and ran statistical tests
on them. He then calculated the mean value and found much
to his surprise (or shock) that the crowd collectively found
that the poor old fat ox weighed 1,197 pounds. Its actual
weight was just one pound more: 1,198. "The result seems
more creditable to the trustworthiness of a democratic judgment
than might have been expected." And thus did the effete
gentlemen from Plymouth discover the wisdom of the crowd.
James
Surowiecki recalls Galton's experiment on an autumnal afternoon
as a perfect introduction to his remarkable and fascinating
polemic on the wisdom that two heads are clearly better than
one. Or put another way: There is something to be said for
groupthink, properly understood.
Surowiecki,
a financial writer for the New Yorker, thinks that groups
or better yet aggregates of individuals can
collectively make wise decisions. Wisdom is more widespread
than we think. Surowiecki finds the wisdom of crowds at work
in Iowa Electronic Markets and Google; the open software movement
and most collaborative scientific research.
But
more telling is how, without any central authority, we manage
each day to walk into crowds of pedestrians without knocking
them down or drive upon interstate highways without much damage
considering the sheer numbers of people on the road. People,
if we care to look, have a great ability to coordinate their
actions without many rules or rulers.
Nobel
Prize economist Vernon Smith proved that "naive, unsophisticated
agents" can coordinate themselves "to achieve complex,
mutually beneficial ends." Surowiecki is a market enthusiast
and he wishes more people could marvel, like Frederic Bastiat,
at how well markets move products from the people who can
produce them most cheaply to the people who want them most
fervently. "What's mysterious is that this is supposed
to happen without anyone seeing the whole picture of what
the market is doing, and without anyone knowing in advance
what a good answer will look like," notes the author.
On
the other hand for example, he shows where there is no wisdom:
NASA (as it confronted the Challenger and Columbia catastrophes),
network television executives (who continue to rely on the
increasingly obsolete Neilson television ratings system),
movie theater owners (who refuse to part with a one-price-fits-all
strategy for turkeys like Gigli) and Long Term Capital
Management, the hedge fund that nearly brought the world to
financial calamity in the late 1990s. These, along with stock
market bubbles are examples, where very smart people working
collectively produce poor results.
Surowiecki's
thesis runs up against the mythic ethos of someone like Henry
David Thoreau who once said, "The mass never comes up
to the standard of its best member, but on the contrary degrades
itself to a level with the lowest." The author Charles
Mackay of the 1841 classic, Extraordinary Popular Delusions
and the Madness of Crowds scoffed that crowds could ascertain
anything. More recently, Ralph Cordiner, former chairman of
General Electric, once boasted that "if you can name
for me one great discovery or decision that was made by a
committee, I will find you the one man in that committee who
had the lonely insight while he was shaving or on his
way to work, or maybe while the rest of the committee was
chattering away the lonely insight that solved the
problem and was the basis for the decision."
What exactly did MacKay and Thoreau and later Galton and Cordiner
overlook? While there is much room for the pursuits of entrepreneurs
and rugged individualists (Surowiecki gives an approving nod
to "methodological individualism"), the author places
enormous faith in a synthesis where independence even
to the point of irrationality within a group guards
against errors. More specifically, the more influence a member
of a group has upon another member the less likely good decisions
will be made.
He writes, "Diversity and independence are important
because the best collective decisions are the product of disagreement
and contest, not consensus and compromise. An intelligent
group, especially when confronted with cognition problems,
does not ask its members to modify their positions in order
to let the group reach a decision everyone can be happy with.
Instead, if figures out how to use mechanisms like
market prices, or intelligent voting systems to aggregate
and produce collective judgments that represent not what any
one person in the group thinks but rather, in some sense,
what they all think. Paradoxically, the best way for a group
to be smart is for each person in it to think and act as independently
as possible."
This is distinct from the idea of herding. Professional money
managers rarely beat the market because they herd and according
to Surowiecki "in doing so, they destroy whatever information
advantage they might have had, since the mimicking managers
are not trading on their own information but are relying on
the information of others."
To make his argument cogent and compelling, Surowiecki relies
on the work of many economists from diverse schools of thought
from John Maynard Keynes to Ronald Coase to the growing adherents
of behavioral economics. But no one can approach the enormous
influence of the Austrian Frederich von Hayek upon Surowiecki
where the Nobel Laureate's theory of market coordination holds
sway.
In
his seminal work "The Uses of Knowledge in Society,"
Hayek stressed the importance of how a price system could
coordinate the resources of many disparate individuals.(1)
This was possible because many of the players without
regard to a central authority retained "tacit
knowledge." This knowledge emerges from the experience
of each player and is often contingent on local conditions
that no administrator can replicate. This tacit knowledge
is crucial to efficiency because the ensuing order enables
producers to properly allocate their products to consumers
who are most willing to pay for them. A market system based
on prices that serve as signals demonstrates the allocative
superiority of capitalism over socialism.
But
as Surowiecki acknowledges, Hayek did not view 'the market
as a kind of giant calculating machine." For Hayek, the
virtues of the market lay in its decentralized nature with
buyers and sellers achieving their ends only through the price
system. Surowiecki believes, with good reason, that Hayek's
fear of socialism prevented him from realizing the benefits
of aggregating diverse opinions to glean the wisdom of the
crowd. Hayek was right to worry about socialist calculation
but he did not foresee the dominance of technology and the
way that technology could be used to centralize decision making
away from his decentralized ideal. Both Hayek and Surowiecki
rely on the premise that local knowledge intuition,
limited personal information, rule of thumb are the
endgame of coordination. The decline in price for computing
power has enabled industrial organizations to substitute aggregated
information for local knowledge
The
legal scholar Richard Epstein notes that this shift away from
local knowledge is the result of cheaper and readily available
technology. "It is not that local knowledge is disreputable.
It is that it can become ineffective in at least some walks
of life relative to more systemic, number-crunching attacks
on certain problems." (2) The increasing role of technology
deployed by both governments and corporations even at the
expense of local knowledge does not diminish Surowiecki's
brilliant "autobiography of an idea." The author's
thesis is vital because it renews a faith in a democratic
ethos that can generate as good a solution as that of an expert,
public official or a computer. "State a moral case for
a ploughman and a professor, wrote Thomas Jefferson, "the
former will decide it as well and often better than the latter
because he has not been led astray by artificial rules."
(Endnotes)
1 For an exposition of Hayek's argument in favor of local
knowledge, see F.A. Hayek, "The Use of Knowledge in Society,"
American Economic Review, XXXV, No. 4; September, 1945, pp.
519-30; Internet, available at http://www.econlib.org/library/Essays/hykKnw1.html,
accessed February 28, 2005.
2 Richard A. Epstein, "The Uses and Limits of Local Knowledge:
A Cautionary Note on Hayek," New York University Journal
of Law and Liberty, I, No. 0; Internet; available at http://www.law.nyu.edu/journals/liberty/Images/11%20-%20Epstein.pdf;accessed
February 28, 2005.
|